Bringing European Democracy Back In—Or How to Read the German Constitutional Court's Lisbon Treaty Ruling

AuthorErik Oddvar Eriksen,John Erik Fossum
Date01 March 2011
Published date01 March 2011
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0386.2010.00549.x
eulj_549153..171
Bringing European Democracy Back
In—Or How to Read the German
Constitutional Court’s Lisbon
Treaty Ruling
Erik Oddvar Eriksen and John Erik Fossum*
Abstract: This article critically examines the democratic theory that informs the German
Federal Constitutional Court’s Lisbon Treaty ruling. This is needed because the ruling is
ambiguous with regard to which type of democracy applies to which type of Union. In
order to analyse the ruling we establish three models of what European democracy
possibly can amount to: audit democracy based on the EU as a derivative of the Member
States; a multinational federal state; or a regional cosmopolitan polity? The court’s
depiction of the EU does not fit as well as we would expect when labeled as a derivative
entity due to the important legislative role of the European Parliament. The EU’s legal
supranationalism points in the direction of a federation, but the court’s argumentation
does not lend support to this notion. The court models democracy on a rather specific set
of institutional presuppositions that are derived from the parliamentary model of democ-
racy associated with the sovereign nation state. At the same time, the court operates with
a conception of a changing state sovereignty that unfolds more in line with cosmopolitan
rather than with classical Westphalian statist principles.
Introduction
The European integration process has been rightly cast as ‘integration through law’.
Each major step of integration has been legally encoded, and legal interpretation and
application have furthered the integration process. The process has many sources and
drivers, national no less than European. European integration was authorised through
special provisions in the initial founder states’ national constitutions.1European law’s
legitimacy draws on the common constitutional traditions of the Member States, and
the Member States still consider themselves as ‘masters of the treaties’. Court rulings,
also national constitutional court rulings give a strong steer to the integration process.
* Erik O. Eriksen is Director and Professor of political science at ARENA—Centre for European Studies,
University of Oslo. John Erik Fossum is Professor of political science at ARENA—Centre for European
Studies, University of Oslo.
1F. Schorkopf, refers in the article ‘The European Union as an Association of Sovereign States: Karlsruhe’s
Ruling on the Treaty of Lisbon’, (2009) 8 German Law Journal 1219, to the ‘German constitution, which
from the beginning was distinguished by its “visionary openness towards Europe”...’.
European Law Journal, Vol. 17, No. 2, March 2011, pp. 153–171.
© 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
A national constitutional court may: (a) affirm the integration that has been wrought;
(b) reject it; (c) set limits to further integration; or (d) direct it in a particular way. These
considerations are relevant when considering the German Court’s Lisbon Treaty ruling
because the treaty amends the basic legal framework and operating conditions for the
Union. In this connection, it also matters that the Supreme Court in question was the
German Federal Constitutional Court because Germany is such a central member of
the EU.
The Federal German Constitutional Court (GCC) was asked to consider the effects
of European integration on German constitutional democracy.2This was effectively
also a question of European-level democracy. In order to settle the question of whether
the emerging system of rule in Europe undermines German democracy, it was impor-
tant to establish the democratic character and quality of the emerging European
system. Thus, as the case was framed, the GCC would have to address the question of
the democratic legitimacy of the integration process and of the EU. This entailed also
taking a stance on the question of the type of polity that had emerged in Europe.
How well the GCC did is hotly disputed, and has also been profoundly criticised.3
The GCC’s ruling is backed up by a comprehensive body of text to explain and justify
it. The court here also spells out in more detail its conception of the EU and what it
considers as appropriate—and inappropriate—integration. The GCC underlines that
the EU is in democratic terms a derivative of the Member States. The EU draws its
democratic legitimacy from the representative-democratic systems in place in the
Member States.4Further, the court interprets the present status of integration as one
that does not substantiate the notion of the EU as a federal state; neither does it contain
the necessary democratic elements to justify federal statehood.
In this sense, the court operates as a democratic theorist of sorts. It devises a
normative conception of democracy (electoral democracy embedded in a unified
people) that serves as the relevant standard for the assessment of the relationship
between German democracy and the system of European rule. The court applies its
conception of democracy to how it understands the EU as a political entity and a
system of rule. These are highly contested issues. Normative theorists do not agree on
any one set of standards; analysts and policy makers disagree on the viability of
democracy at the European level; and analysts, policymakers and citizens alike do not
agree on the kind of polity the EU is. The court has taken a stance in these debates.
The court brings democracy to bear on the European integration process but what is
the nature of the democratic theory of the Euro-polity that we can discern from the
court’s ruling? Our concern in this article is to examine critically the democratic theory
2‘The judgment focuses on the connection between the democratic system prescribed by the Basic Law on
the level of the federation and the level of independent rule which has been reached at the European level;
see Federal Constitutional Court’s Press office, Press Release No 72/2009 of 30 June 2009, available at
http://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/pressemitteilungen/bvg09-072en.html.
3See the various contributions by C. Schönberger, F. Schorkopf, D. Halberstam and C. Möllers, and M.
Niedobitek in the Special Section on the Federal Constitutional Court’s Lisbon case in (2009) 8 German
Law Journal 1201–1308. See also contributions by D. Chalmers and U. Liebert in A. Fischer-Lescano, C.
Joerges and A. Wonka (eds), The German Constitutional Court’s Lisbon Ruling: Legal and Political Science
Perspectives, ZERP Discussion Paper 1/2010.
4The GCC notes that: ‘[a]s long as, consequently, no uniform European people, as the subject of legitimi-
sation, can express its majority will in a politically effective manner that takes due account of equality in
the context of the foundation of a European federal state, the peoples of the European Union, which are
constituted in their Member States, remain the decisive holders of public authority, including Union
authority’; see Federal Constitutional Court’s Press office, op cit n2supra.
European Law Journal Volume 17
154 © 2011 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT