Practical Reasoning, Impartiality and the European Patent Office: The Legal Regulation of Biotechnology

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/eulj.12005
Date01 November 2012
AuthorKaterina Sideri
Published date01 November 2012
Practical Reasoning, Impartiality and the
European Patent Office: The Legal
Regulation of Biotechnology
Katerina Sideri*
Abstract: The article argues in favour of a different conceptualisation of the role of the
European Patent Office, and of the mode of reasoning that the EPO ought to deploy, so
as to decide cases concerning the patentability of gene related inventions such as diag-
nostic tests, and questions regarding the regulation of therapeutic cloning. Richardson’s
model of specifying norms offers an important alternative to the models based on
cost-benefit analysis and neutral application of the appropriate norm by administrative
agencies. Specificationism stresses the importance of revising the ends of policy, coming
up with a new norm, the product of creative synthesis of the content of conflicting norms.
The article adds to this model the idea that the revision of ends requires a strong
deliberative democracy, based on the notion of the practically wise regulator, who can
apply principles correctly, as these cannot be usefully applied in difficult situations
by people who lack experience, insight, and character. Given the current discussion to
establish a unitary EU patent, the thesis advanced here is that the patent system in
Europe ought to endorse elements of deliberative democracy, enhancing the importance
of civil society in the European decision making processes.
I Introduction
Who ought to decide whether it is desirable or not to patent inventions relating to
genes, such as diagnostic tests, or inventions relating to therapeutic cloning, involving
the destruction of 14-day embryos? The obvious answer would be that this is a job for
the legislature, such as the European Parliament and the Council of the European
Union (for EU legislation such as the Biotechnology Directive),1and the Diplomatic
Conference of the Contracting States in the case of an international agreement such
as the European Patent Convention (EPC). However, in Europe, neither the Biotech-
nology Directive nor the EPC provides us with clear answers to these matters, for the
technologies they seek to regulate currently manifest a kind of plasticity that law
not only has serious difficulty in apprehending, but also the power to stifle, at least
temporarily. The Biotechnology Directive prohibits research on the embryo with a
* Associate Research Fellow, Centre for Socio-Legal Studies, University of Oxford, UK.
1Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the Legal
Protection of Biotechnological Inventions.
bs_bs_banner
European Law Journal, Vol. 18, No. 6, November 2012, pp. 821–843.
© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
commercial end, yet it is not clear whether therapeutic cloning ought to be banned on
this basis. The EPC stipulates that diagnosis and treatment are excluded from pat-
entability, yet there is controversy as to the exact way this provision applies in the
case of diagnostic tests using patented genetic technology. It appears that in these and
many other cases, legal regulation will have to gradually evolve; biotechnology is a
new science, and even scientists cannot foretell the exact direction it will take in the
future, hence we could assume that national courts2and the European Patent Office
(EPO) will gradually develop case-law addressing these issues, once we have more
information. Yet the problem is not only that we do not know enough about these
technologies; importantly, there is profound public disagreement about the ethics of
promoting such technologies. Interestingly,3patent law in Europe stipulates that a
patent may not be granted if it is deemed to be of immoral nature. Public perception
of potential benefits and risks is strong and emotional; environmentalists, animal
welfare groups, religious groups, scientists and many others all suggest different views
as to the optimal way to regulate these technologies.
Following the diagnosis of discretionary powers, value pluralism and information
limits, we can return to the question asked at the beginning: who ought to decide how
we go about regulating these technologies? The first response to this question could be
that in cases where there is deep disagreement because of competing values, public
discussion is important, so that we find some common ground on the basis of which
we will begin exchanging views, so as to finally arrive at a conclusion acceptable to
all. This is obviously an argument against judicial activism. We do not need a final,
conclusive answer in the form delivered by courts; rather, in cases of uncertainty as to
the nature and number of parameters that will shape how we understand important
goods, (such as the good of health), and the way these goods relate to new technolo-
gies, we need to be given the opportunity to discuss again and again as a society how
broad legislative mandates ought to be specified in concrete contexts. This is because
specifying is a learning process on both sides: on the side of the law and on the side
of social groups, which will have to seek accommodation of their views, and possibly
revise them in the course of public discussion. Specifying the ends of policy will have
to be an ongoing project, so that the law does not crystallise the elusive, and the
public is given the opportunity to reappraise its values. When patent law regulates
inventions in the field of biotechnology, it brings foreword important questions as to
the proper way to come to grips with the good of health. The latter means many
things for different people, and its content changes overtime. Patents eventually
regulate things, such as who has access to expensive diagnostic tests, whether and
under what circumstances human health is more important than animal welfare, or
the conditions under which patents involving the destruction of 14-day blastocysts
ought to be allowed.
2Of course, in the case of the Biotechnology Directive, Member States have the discretion to interpret
general terms such as ‘ordre public’ in a manner consistent with their legal values and traditions when
implementing these in national legislation. However, national courts will still have to answer important
questions such as the ones relating to definitions of ‘discovery’ and ‘invention.’
3Unlike the US patent law and Japanese patent laws, which do not have similar provisions. For the
argument against including the morality provision in patent laws, see D.M. Gitter, ‘Led Astray by the
Moral Compass: Incorporating Morality into European Union Biotechnology Patent Law’, (2001) 19
Berkeley Journal of International Law 1; B.D. Emerson, ‘Protecting Society from Patently Offensive
Inventions: The Risk of Reviving the Moral Utility Doctrine’, (2004) 89 Cornell Law Review 685.
European Law Journal Volume 18
822 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT