The Argument from Transnational Effects II: Establishing Transnational Democracy

Date01 July 2010
AuthorAlexander Somek
Published date01 July 2010
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0386.2010.00514.x
eulj_514375..394
The Argument from Transnational Effects
II: Establishing Transnational Democracy*
Alexander Somek**
Abstract: This article continues with a discussion of what the author calls the argument
from transnational effects. It says that supranational or transnational forms of integra-
tion, in particular market integration, are desirable on account of democracy itself.
National democracies find themselves thereby forced to confront and to internalise the
externalities that they cause for each other. A fortiori, democracy becomes supposedly
emancipated from the confines of the nation state.
This article examines the argument critically at a general level. The situation under
consideration concerns all cases in which, regardless of whether there is movement or not,
the acts of one democracy adversely impact on the interests of others.
The article tries to identify instances where the harm is tied to a failure of representation
in a transnational context and not caught by the harm principle, broadly understood.
In order to calibrate the argument’s scope the article resorts to the principle of univer-
salisation. The guiding intuition is that so long as the act of one democracy is morally
justified on the basis of this principle, the argument from transnational effects does not
apply. Hence the argument is of no avail where the impact of one democracy on another
is perfectly legitimate. This would be the case, for example, when the effects are too
insignificant to require any debate.
Determining the range of legitimate impact is a core question of transnational consti-
tutional law. Any such determination presupposes mutually shared interest definitions.
More often than not, however, the relevant interest definitions underlying universalisation
are debatable. Therefore, it appears to be inevitable, at first glance, to have relations of
transnational interdependency matched by transnational democratic processes.
The article then goes on to identify three different types of universalitation with refer-
ence to what can be regarded as their respective anchor. Simple universalisation is based
upon shared interest definitions. Reflexive universalisation involves common views of
* Earlier versions of this article were presented at a conference at the Berlin Institute for Advanced Study,
at an in-house faculty workshop at the University of Iowa and as part of the International Legal Theory
Colloquium at New York University Law School. I owe a debt of gratitude to colleagues who provided
me with critical feedback, in particular to Arthur Bonfield, Armin von Bogdandy, Ann Estin, Herbert
Hovenkamp, Benedict Kingsbury, Mattias Kumm, Todd E. Pettys and Joseph Weiler. I should also like
to acknowledge how much I benefited from having been part of a group of ‘constitutionalists’ that was
resident at the Berlin Institute during the academic year of 2007/08. Attending a weekly conversation with
Petra Dobner, Dieter Grimm, Bogdan Iancu, Martin Loughlin, Fritz W. Scharpf, Gunther Teubner and
Rainer Wahl has been highly conducive to the clarification of my constitutional ideas.
** University of Iowa, College of Law.
European Law Journal, Vol. 16, No. 4, July 2010, pp. 375–394.
© 2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
oneself (and others). Self-transcending universalisation is grounded in the desire to live in
a free society.
Reflexive universalisation requires to extend mutual sympathy. From this perspective,
transnational democratic processes are tantamount to nation-building. However, one
would commit a sentimentalist fallacy if one were to conclude that mutual sympathy in and
of itself engenders an expansion of mutual responsibility.
The article argues that with regard to the third type of universalisation the institution-
alisation of transnational democratic procedures cannot be justified. It would threaten to
undermine various conceptions of a free society. It is argued that for the sake of the
realisation of equal citizenship the argument from transnational effects actually needs to
endorse the existence of bounded democratic communities. Unbounded transnational
democracy would exercise an adverse effect on citizenship.
It also turns out that the argument from transnational effects, in its uncorrected form,
remains haunted by the dilemma that the type of democracy that is envisaged by it
becomes easily absorbed by administrative processes.
The article concludes that the argument from transnational effects, correctly under-
stood, has a more modest import than its proponents would have us believe. Rather than
supporting the release of democracy from its national bounds, it helps to explain why the
co-existence of bounded democratic polities remains essential to equal citizenship. More
forceful versions of transnational integration graft onto political societies elements that
are not genuinely democratic and strangely reminiscent of different forms of rule. These
are forms of rule that Aristotle would not have called ‘political’, for they do not involve the
exercise of power by equals over equals.
I The Argument Restated
In the previous article, the exploration of the argument from transnational effects has
mainly focused on the substantive economic due process situation, on the one hand,
and the Bolkestein situation, on the other. In the first situation, economic actors wish
to import into their country of residence laws from other national jurisdictions whose
application is more favourable to their doings. I argued that they cannot avail them-
selves of the support of the argument from transnational effects. In the Bolkestein
situation, by contrast, economic actors basically wish to export their laws to the
country in which they are going to do business. They are also not in a position to claim
the argument’s support. This is not a surprising result. I surmise that most of us would
have been intuitively inclined to take the revised virtual representation argument for
granted and to accept that whoever initiates encounters with a foreign democracy, for
example, by moving a good into it, has reason to respect its laws.
But these conclusions by no means establish that the argument is devoid of a proper
sphere of application. Maybe I have in the first article only explored marginal cases,
and the paradigmatic situation envisaged by the argument from transnational effects is
altogether different.
Here is a statement of the argument by one of its proponents:1
Under conditions of complex interdependencies, a major shortcoming of the democratic nation-state is
the negligence of its external effects. Individual state actions [a]ffect other states and societies without
1Neyer in C. Joerges and J. Neyer, ‘“Deliberative Supranationalism” Revisited’, (2006) 2006/20 EUI
Working Paper Law 2.
European Law Journal Volume 16
376 © 2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT