The Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence edited by George Duke Robert P. George Published by Cambridge University Press, 2017, 458 pp., £31.99, paperback.

Date01 April 2018
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/reel.12236
AuthorNikolas Sellheim
Published date01 April 2018
THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO NATURAL LAW
JURISPRUDENCE edited by George Duke and Robert
P. George
Published by Cambridge University Press, 2017, 458 pp., £31.99, paperback.
I think it is impossible to definitively state how many times in my life I
have been confronted with the claim of something not being natural.
Of course, homosexuality is often cited, alongside abortion and artifi-
cial insemination, as disrupting the naturalprocess of procreation.
Even more extreme arguments are advanced in support of the abor-
tion of disabled children, on the grounds that they have lost their nat-
uralability to survive. In other words, there appears to be reference to
the natural order of things, to a law of nature, which supports specific
approaches to highly emotional and morality-infused contexts.
But I dare say that it is less popularly known that an entire legal
theory, legal or philosophical tradition, is rooted in the nature of
things, so to speak, or a normativity, namely natural law, which has
found its more concrete origins in the writings of Thomas of Aquinas
and is to a large extent characterized by the belief in a divine order.
There is indeed much to criticize about this theory, having garnered
much scholarly literature on the primacy of natural law or positive
law even within this book in Mark C. MurphysTwo Dilemmas of
Natural Law Jurisprudence. Not surprisingly, one of the editors,
Robert P. George, even felt compelled to write the book In Defense
of Natural Law
1
in which he argues his view on the role natural law
plays in matters surrounding justice and morality.
But irrespective of how one approaches or considers natural or
positive law, this book is certainly an extremely insightful account of
the fundamental issues surrounding natural law and moral philoso-
phy and offers contributions by some of the biggest names of the
newnatural law theory, which emerged during the second half of
the twentieth century, such as the editors themselves, John Finnis
and Robert Alexy, to name a few. This volume comprises 16 chap-
ters, which are subdivided into three parts: Part I considers Founda-
tions; Part II addresses Practical Reason, Normativity and Ethics; and
Part III examines the Law. It may be suggested that after careful
consideration of this far-reaching volume, the reader will be fully
apprised of the origins, theoretical and practical underpinnings as
well as the application of natural law and natural law theory. Inevita-
bly, one must decide on several occasions whether or not to agree
with the claims brought forth by the authors. This, however, is a
very laudable part of academic debate and hopefully stimulates dis-
cussion and further scholarly output. For instance, I was personally
rather troubled by Georges assertion that natural law should con-
tribute to the reversal of moral decline, which, for example, mani-
fests itself in abortion. Likewise, it may be contested whether
natural law should serve as a tool to revitalize and protect the mar-
riage culture, beginning with the preservation of marriage as the
conjugal union of husband and wife(at 70). In other words, George
prima facie appears to equate feminism, gender equality or womens
self-control over their bodies with moral decline, which inevitably
engenders significant political and ideological dimensions.
Be that as it may, while there are specific contexts such as the
above, that are rooted in natural law theory which I cannot condone,
the philosophical and ultimately moral dimensions of natural law the-
ory can be considered as constituting general principles of law,
thereby also serving as a source of international law.
2
Notwithstand-
ing the role one may ascribe to natural law theory, I found this vol-
ume particularly engaging and thought-provoking due to its
profound philosophical angles and the associated moral dimensions
of law, law-making and legal interpretation. Writing as a legal anthro-
pologist, I am especially happy to see how the discussions and schol-
arly excursions into the realm of natural law make such frequent and
fundamental reference to the social, which makes the notion of the
human being (or nature, for that matter) within the legalbetter
comprehensible. One way or the other, the book is multidisciplinary.
For instance, Jonathan Crowe in his chapter on Metaphysical Foun-
dations of Natural Law Theories,byinter alia using the example of a
chair, deals with the properties of artefacts and how their features
and those of humans enable them to be used in a certain way. By
linking these intentional and functional attributes of a chair with the
legal, Crowe contributes to the theoretical advancement of legal
anthropology after all, what he describes as intentional or func-
tional attributes of an artefact have been termed affordance theory
in anthropology: a stone can be perceived just as a stone. It can,
however, also be perceived as a building block for a house, as a tool
or as a weapon. It is the stone which affords specific characteristics
and it is up to the human or animal to respond to these afford-
ances.
3
By referencing the building of a wall which is ultimately
replaced by a legal barrier (at 122), the affordance theory has indeed
found its way into legal contexts.
Overall, I found the premises of the authors of this volume to
be overly focused on the deterrence- or sanction-based characteris-
tics of law. The aforementioned chapter by Crowe, for example,
states that a goodlaw is only that kind of law which is legally
binding, while Thomas Pink in Hume, Virtue and Natural Law
remarks that [n]atural law ... directs us in a way that is recogniz-
ably legal by imposing demands on how we act(at 187); and N.E.
Simmonds characterizes Law as an Idea We Live By. In line with
other scholars, I would ascribe many more functions to the law,
one of which is an expressive one, which combines characteristics
of deterrence and sanctions with coordination and information.
4
In
order to make the addressees complicit, and to achieve the good,
[l]aw is of course not content to merely describe or comment on
BOOK REVIEWS
|
99
DOI: 10.1111/reel.12236
1
RP George, In Defense of Natural Law (Oxford University Press 1999).
2
D Bodansky, J Brunn
ee and L Rajamani, International Climate Change Law (Oxford Univer-
sity Press 2017) 37, fn 10.
3
J Gibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Houghton Mifflin 1979).
4
RH McAdams, The Expressive Powers of Law: Theories and Limits (Harvard University Press
2016).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT